In Partial Fulfillment for the Degree of Bachelor
of Arts and Distinction in
Philosophy
Seth Miller
December, 1997
View the entire thesis as one document for easy printing.
All physical theory contains, either implicitly or explicitly, metaphysical components. No theory that concerns itself with the physical world--its forms, properties, interactions, or changes--can exist without including, on a fundamental but often tacit level, one or more purely metaphysical assumptions. In the contemporary world physics is often thought to be the hardest of the 'hard' sciences, which is another way of saying that physics is that discipline most rigorously concerned with understanding the physical truths of the universe. This, along with the consistent validation of physical truths in their applied form ("technology"), easily leads to the conception that physics has some particularly authoritative claim to insight concerning the ontology of the universe.
Nevertheless, a close examination of any physical theory, no matter how "proven"
or "tested" will yield various underlying assumptions that can only be described
as metaphysical. "Gravity"1 is a perfect example: ask any physicist if gravity
exists, and the answer will be affirmative; ask what gravity is, and suddenly the
responses become much stranger. Some might relate that gravity is an inherent
property of mass, a "field" with attractive properties whose intensity decreases
in exact proportion to the square of the distance from the center of the object
of mass; others might mention space-time and the General Theory of Relativity and
how mass distorts space-time to create something that looks like a "force". When
pressed, however, it is mildly shocking to discover that, although the actual
existence of gravity is entirely unquestioned, its particular ontology is quite
mysterious. We don't really know what gravity is--in fact, Einstein showed that
gravitational frames and accelerated frames can be treated identically (the math
is the same in both cases).
Gravity is an old theory created as an explanation for otherwise unexplained
phenomena (for example the observation that if one drops an object, it will
always fall towards the Earth and not into the sky or parallel to the ground).
We assume that something is happening in the universe to create these peculiar
events, and we call it "gravity". Unfortunately, the creation of the term in
conjunction with its subsequent widespread usage has resulted in the popular
reification of gravity--it has been promoted from a concept to an actually
existing force in the universe.
In general it would seem that in order to retain explanatory power a concept must
have an ontological status that is more fundamental than the phenomena it
explains. This is true not necessarily because of any logical rules, but because
of the particular constitution of those that require explanation: namely, humans.
The argument may be something like: "because it is obvious that objects actually
fall towards the Earth, gravity too, must actually exist, because isn't that what
causes the objects to fall towards the Earth? And besides, if gravity did not
exist, then what would explain this phenomenon?". The incompleteness of the
logic is glaring, but it can slide by unnoticed due to the unquestioning
acceptance of the existence of "gravity". When examined critically, the theory
of gravity remains metaphysical--its status cannot exceed that of an explanatory
concept--one that can be more or less useful, to be sure, but a concept
nonetheless.
The answer to the question "...isn't that what causes the objects to fall towards
the Earth?" is negative. That objects fall towards the Earth is an empirical
observation; the theory of gravity began as an attempt to provide an explanation
of why this is so. Unfortunately, to have the concept of gravity does not
necessarily result in the fact of gravity; rather, it placates those people who
ask the question "Why do objects fall towards the Earth?" by posing as a valid,
ontological "reason" for the observed events. Yet we still do not know what
gravity is, only that in order to explain certain phenomena, it is valuable to
posit something like what we know of now as "gravity".
Once the concept of gravity exists, it becomes possible to test its applicability
in various ways, and through a careful process, the idea can be refined. New
observations are made, which are subsequently compared with and related to older
observations, and depending upon the specifics, the idea of gravity is modified
to fit the new observations (for example that massless particles are affected by
the 'attractive' properties that were thought only to apply to other bodies of
mass).
It is often assumed (by physicists and philosophers alike) that physics poses
only "What?" and "How?" questions, and in fact physics, abstracted from its
existence as a human creation, does relate to physical truths in this manner. But
physics as a discipline cannot be completely abstracted in this way, and when
placed in its context as a human discipline, the fundamental motive for physical
theory is seen to arise not from "What?" or "How?" but from the question "Why?".
To continually search for answers to this most difficult of queries inevitably
leads beyond the conservative boundaries of physics and into the speculative
realm of metaphysics, which also asks "Why?" In fact, metaphysics can be seen as
an attempt to create a framework in which the question "Why?" can be answered
directly, through the establishment of some sort of 'ultimate' upon which all
explanation can and must finally rest. Still, as a general rule, an adequate
metaphysical scheme must be able to take into account what we know about reality
through physics; if it does not, then the scheme is inadequate and must be
rejected or revised.
Whitehead knew this, and when he brought his metaphysics into clear formulation
in the late 1920's, he made a remarkable effort to include what he knew from the
developing field of physics. Between then and now, however, such significant
advances in physics have taken place that it seems that Whitehead has been left
entirely in the subatomic dust. In particular significant advances have occurred
in the highly non-intuitive and extremely complex field of quantum mechanics--one
of the most metaphysical realms in all of modern science and therefore one quite
congenially related to Whitehead's own temperament.
On to Quantum Mechanics.
Counter provided free by Digits.com |