How would Whitehead respond to Aspect's experiment and the violation of Bell's Inequality? At first it would appear that Whitehead's theory of actual entities (I will refer to them as actual occasions from here on, as 'occasion' is more accurate than 'entity' in nearly all senses) is doomed to failure because of its inherent realism, and its seeming inability to account for the strange quantum effects that are observed in modern experiments. But the problem of bringing Whitehead up to date with the modern physical situation may really be more a question of adapting our own understanding to that of Whitehead's in order to see how his metaphysics might apply.
One of the central problems that physicists deal with is the temptation to hold onto a view of the world that can be squared with our common sense perception of it. Therefore it seems reasonable, for example, to attribute definite properties to objects even while they are unobserved. One way in which physicists are able to explain the strange quantum correlations is to say that there is some way in which the two correlated measurements had a certain cause in their past which brought about the effect of a correlation (essentially saying that the photons were correlated before the measurements). Most physicists will agree that this is a possible explanation--that the rules of the universe as we know them do not prohibit this type of phenomenon. However, it appears that if this explanation is taken, the result is that science itself becomes impossible.
This is so because the explanation that the state of a phenomenon can be explained by a common cause somewhere in the past (however distant) seems to say that we cannot fully explain a phenomenon by examining only its immediate past. It is as if we must give up all certainty in science in order to explain a few details (interpretational details at that!) of quantum mechanics, because we could never know for sure what distant cause could be producing this particular present phenomenon. For this reason, physicists reject this explanation out of hand as quite absurd.
If we take into account Whitehead's view of physics, however, this view deserves a second glance. The important point to consider is what Whitehead calls the "Ontological Principle", which merely states that all phenomena can be traced back to actual occasions themselves and no further--any reason for anything must ultimately and finally rest upon actual occasions and the interactions between them (which is really just to say the actual occasions themselves, since an actual occasion consists almost entirely of relations).
As a result of the Ontological Principle, we must radically change our common
conception that space and time are separate, objective 'dimensions' in which all
events take place. Rather, space and time are properties of the relations
between actual occasions. This is point is absolutely crucial. For Whitehead,
the past is defined relatively for every actual occasion and is not defined by a
blind linear progression through time from the past, through the present, to the
future. The past for this actual occasion is just those actual occasions that
contribute to its process of concrescence. Thus, the resulting objective datum
that is positively prehended from each already satisfied actual occasion in the
initial datum by a particular actual occasion becomes the past for that actual
occasion.12 Similarly, the future is defined as just those actual occasions that
will prehend this concrescing actual occasion. Time in this sense can be seen as
the result of a type of causal link between individual actual occasions. Thus,
there is no past that is more or less distant, because the past arises relatively
for each actual occasion in its process of concrescence.
In Aspect's experiment, the photons would be considered enduring objects (objects
consisting of actual occasions that exist in a particular type of simple
relationship). They would be enduring objects that, although spatially
separated, were part of a larger society. Following from the Copenhagen
interpretation, the society in which the enduring objects exist as a sub-society
is the 'measurement situation' itself, where it would be incorrect to abstract
the particular photons from the entire society in which they are a part. (To
assume that these particular photons will behave exactly like every other photon,
even like ones not in the experiment, is a good example of what Whitehead calls
the 'fallacy of misplaced concreteness'.)
Saying that the photons are part of a larger society is actually to say nothing
other than that the past for each actual occasion in each enduring object is
similar, to the point at which there exists a common cause for the particular
behaviour of the photons. This common cause is just the fact that the photons
are part of the society of the measurement situation from which they cannot be
isolated. The past, being just those prehensions that contribute to the
satisfaction of an actual occasion, is highly influential upon the final outcome
of that actual occasion. By looking at an actual occasion's past, we examine
reasons for why that actual occasion came to its particular satisfaction. An
enduring object, because it has very little freedom, is extremely influenced by
its past, to the point at which it seems to act in a determinate manner (more on
this below). Thus the past for an enduring object (the photon) that is part of a
larger society (the measurement situation) is intimately entangled with the past
of the entire society itself. The actual occasions of the enduring object take
into account (prehend) an objective datum consisting mostly of other satisfied
actual occasions which are part of the larger society, whose influence causes the
enduring objects to behave in a correlated manner. The correlations occur
because of laws internal to the society, which arise from the relations between
the actual occasions in the society itself.
One reason that physicists are so worried about the possibility that there might
be some sort of faster-than-light signaling taking place behind the scenes arises
from an innate (and highly classical) propensity to consider the photons as
separate and individual phenomenon. Given this type of conception, it appears
that the photons must be 'communicating' in some way if we are to explain the
correlation. Neils Bohr took a step in the right direction when he determined
that the photons couldn't really be considered individual photons unless they
were part of a measurement situation set up to detect this property (of
individuality). As related above, Bohr noted that rather than conceiving of some
sort of connection between two individual and spatially separated photons, it
would be more accurate to think about the photons as part of a larger situation
which included the measuring apparatus, and that no property of a quantum system
was definite and real unless it was itself part of such a larger system. In this
instance the possibility for faster-than-light signaling need not take place,
because it is the situation of the entire measurement (including the measurement
of both photons) that gives rise to the correlation. If only one photon is
measured, the correlations do not occur.
Then how can Whitehead deal with the claim that to explain the correlations by
attributing to them a certain type of past results in the death of all possible
prediction? This critique, arising from the search for an explanation of the
violation of Bell's Inequality, is also aimed at Whitehead more generally by all
sciences concerned with certain prediction.
The problem arises because for Whitehead, there are no unchangeable and immutable
laws of physics that must be obeyed by actual occasions. According to the
Ontological Principle, it is in fact just the reverse: the laws of physics arise
from the actual occasions themselves, just as space-time (and everything else)
does. This in conjunction with the idea that actual occasions are not fully
determinate, but have some level of freedom, results in the fact that the laws of
physics are not constant but rather evolutionary, in the sense that they
evolve--they are part of the changing process, which is the reality.
This fact directly results in another critique of similar spirit from a slightly
different angle: in the scientific realm it is an advantage for a theory to have
predictive powers. If a theory cannot add something to our knowledge of the
future, then it is powerless and can serve no purpose. Yet Whitehead's
metaphysical scheme is exactly that which cannot take part in the realm of
prediction. For Whitehead, a metaphysical scheme must, in principle, be able to
account for both all of actual experience, and all of possible experience.
Because of this, and as a consequence of its very nature, a metaphysical scheme
cannot be predictive, but must function only in an explanatory capacity.
"Metaphysics is nothing but the description of the generalities which apply to
all the details of practice." (Process and Reality:13)
For those who are accustomed to the ways of methodological science, this would
appear to be a grave fault. It would seem that any theory that disclaimed in
principle all predictive power should be given up immediately, as it would be
utterly useless--but useless only to physicists who are preoccupied with definite
prediction and measurement. Metaphysics provides us with an ability to
understand the physics in relation to other types of knowledge, and perhaps more
importantly, other types of experience. The need for this type of relation (that
metaphysics provides) is obvious today merely from the fact that the major
debates surrounding quantum mechanics in the present (and for the past 50 years)
are all basically metaphysical in character, if not explicitly so in substance.
Even though metaphysics doesn't necessarily add anything to our knowledge of the
future, it does contribute much to our knowledge of the present. Far from being
vestigial, Whitehead would argue that metaphysics is actually quite necessary for
a complete understanding of experience (more on this in my conclusion).
It seems then that Whitehead would give up the assumption of parameter
independence, while keeping reality and a version of locality. Or rather,
Whitehead never would have assumed parameter independence to begin with. Because
space is a consequence of the relations between actual occasions, Whitehead is
able to keep locality in the sense that in our present epoch, it just so happens
that space is constructed in certain ways (i.e. has a definite relation to time,
can be 'warped', etc.), and that one of the ways in which it is constructed has
as a consequence a definite non-relative speed for light. In our present epoch,
Bell's assumption of locality (no faster-than-light signaling) seems to be a good
assumption, but due to the fact that actual occasions are not fully bound by any
external environment (since they themselves create that environment), this will
not always necessarily be the case.
This conclusion presents a big problem for physicists who depend upon the fact
that the laws of the universe remain constant. The entire validity of scientific
progress rests upon the assumption that results of a particular experiment, if
set up with sufficient attention to detail, will not vary through time. This
assumption is not generated from within science, but rather is a principle that
allows science to exist in the first place. It arises not a priori, but from the
simple observation of its truth as manifested in the actual world: if we set up
an experiment to detect the speed of light today, its value will be exactly the
same as it was last week, or even last century. If there is any change in
physical law, it is because we become more accurate in our experiments and are
able to see reality more clearly, not because the laws themselves are subject to
change.
Yet if Whitehead's scheme were correct, it would seem plausible that we could, by
performing an experiment at t1, and later at t2, detect some difference that
would correspond to the change in physical law over (Deltat. Yet it seems to be a
fact of nature that whenever we perform the same experiments, no matter when or
where (again provided we set up the experiment with sufficient attention to each
of its elements), the same results occur. Whitehead, however, does appear to be
able to deal with this dilemma.
Physical laws are a consequence of the interactions between actual occasions,
which is to say that they are a consequence of the prehensions of actual
occasions. Whitehead would argue that what we observe to be physical laws are
almost entirely due to the way in which certain actual occasions which form
enduring objects prehend each other. The mode of the prehension in these
instances can be characterized by an inertial power, in fact a tradition,13 from
one actual occasion to another. The propensity for any actual entity to either
follow the tradition or not is directly proportional to its level of freedom
(here referring to the occasion's propensity or ability for novelty). In the
case of systems with very low levels of complexity, such as enduring objects,
this freedom is negligible. For this reason, the tradition is almost always
accepted, as there is insufficient complexity in the string of actual occasions
that constitute the enduring object to allow for the realization of possibilities
outside of those presented by the actual occasion's objective datum.
For example, an electron (an enduring object) always has a negative charge which
is quite invariant. The actual occasions that constitute the electron are in a
sense overwhelmed by the sheer inertial power of the particular objective datum
(which can be characterized as electronic in the present epoch) which it
prehends, and is essentially forced to follow the rules of the tradition that
already exists.
Subatomic particles, like electrons, have as constituents only actual occasions
that are already easily subject to traditional forms (in the sense of electronic
or protonic forms of behaviour--particular types of physical law). A highly
complex actual occasion would almost never become part of a traditional chain (an
enduring object), because it is, by the fact of its complexity, not as
impressionable as actual occasions of a more simple type, and therefore not as
subject to the certain laws which pervade such traditions. The majority of
actual occasions are of the simple, traditional type, and thus obey the laws of
physics--although it is more correct to say that enduring objects are just those
in which the laws of the tradition are realized.
Of course the laws of the tradition need not always be obeyed. If an actual
occasion in an enduring object broke the tradition, some sort of radical change
in the enduring object could be expected. In modern high-energy physics this
might be analogous to particle creation and destruction.
Supplementally, Whitehead relates that God's placement of the subjective aim into
each actual occasion is a principled one. Novelty arises principally in
organisms of high complexity, which have as constituents sub-societies and
sub-sub-societies, all the way down to the simple enduring objects. Such
complexity is built from the bottom up, in the sense that complex organisms
presuppose the existence of the simpler societies (the reverse is not true,
however). Because God has as a goal the expansion of novelty, and because
novelty has a much higher possibility for realization in complex organisms that
require the existence of simple societies and enduring objects, it seems
reasonable to assume that God would willingly place into simpler actual occasions
(like the kind that form enduring objects) subjective aims that were designed not
for the maximization of novelty on the simple level, but rather for the
maximization of novelty on more complex levels. It is a question of harmony: in
order to have intense forms of novelty and experience on one level, such novelty
must be sacrificed on another level. Thus there would be an advantage for God to
place subjective aims into certain actual occasions such that something like
'laws of the universe' exist and exhibit the seemingly immutable character
presently observed.
It is clear that for Whitehead the laws of physics are not constant, but the
relative degree and severity of their change remains undefined. It is quite
possible that the basic laws of physics change only very slowly, as they can be
seen to be more 'entrenched', while, for example, biological laws would have a
tendency to shift more readily, as they exist only in reference to more complex
systems which are more capable of novelty and freedom. And because the
Ontological Principle states that all things, including such laws, are due to
actual occasions and their interactions, a derivative statement results to the
effect that when laws exist for certain types of systems of actual occasions, the
degree of constancy in the particular tradition (the sheer inertial power of the
objective datum) decreases in proportion to the level of complexity (and hence
propensity for novelty) achieved in that particular system of actual occasions.